Tort Theory in Copyright Law: Thinking about Patrick Goold’s Unbundling the “Tort” of Copyright Infringement

Patrick R. Goold, Unbundling the “Tort” of Copyright Infringement 102 Va. L. Rev. 1833 (2016), available at SSRN

Patrick Goold’s Unbundling the “Tort” of Copyright Infringement (“Unbundling”) is an ambitious and remarkably illuminating article. Its central thesis is that “copyright infringement” is best understood as a cover term for five different “copytorts”1 related to the plaintiff’s being a copyright owner. By way of comparison, “trespass” and “nuisance” in tort law are pleaded and articulated with different names even though they both pertain to wrongs related to a plaintiff’s ownership of realty; this is because they are, conceptually and practically, quite different wrongs. Copyright law has never separated out its five different legal wrongs, either through statute or through judicial elaboration, either formally or informally. It has used the one phrase “copyright infringement” indiscriminately for all. It turns out, Goold argues, that much of the confusion and conflict within copyright case law can be traced back to the failure to draw distinctions among the five copytorts. The task of the article is to outline the distinctions, thereby beginning the process of solving a number of doctrinal problems.

The three doctrinal problems Goold presents pertain to audience, harm, and analogy. As to “audience,” the question concerns the observer, or arbiter, or audience that courts should employ to determine whether allegedly infringing material is sufficiently similar to the copyrighted material: must it be such as to cause confusion to a reasonable person, an ordinary consumer, or an expert? As to “harm” (which arises in connection with a fair use defense) the question concerns “‘the effect of the [copyist’s] use upon the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work.’” (P. 1848 (quoting 17 U.S.C § 107 (2012)).) Courts have construed this factor to turn on “whether the copying caused the owner cognizable harm” (Id.); some courts in turn focus upon demand diversion, others on lost fees, and others on reputational, privacy, or other nonfinancial injuries. Finally, as to “analogy,” the question is how copyright infringement ought to be modeled as a legal wrong: is it like trespass, like conversion, like an economic tort or unfair competition, or like unjust enrichment? Continue reading "Tort Theory in Copyright Law: Thinking about Patrick Goold’s Unbundling the “Tort” of Copyright Infringement"

The Plural Tort Structure of Copyright Law

Patrick Goold, Unbundling the ‘Tort’ of Copyright Infringement, 102 Va. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2016), available at SSRN.

What kind of legal wrong is copyright infringement? Scholars tend to unreflectively regard copyright infringement as a tort. In his elegant and insightful recent article, Unbundling the ‘Tort’ of Copyright Infringement, Patrick Goold complicates this received wisdom by applying rigorous conceptual analysis to a body of law—copyright—that is rarely analyzed in those terms. In so doing, Goold invites us to see copyright law in a new and more nuanced light, and also seeks to show that courts’ purportedly scattered approach to infringement may not be so incoherent after all.

The central premise of Goold’s article is simple: the orthodox view of copyright infringement as a single tort mischaracterizes how courts actually resolve infringement cases. Calling on Prosser’s classic disaggregation of privacy into a “gallery of torts,” Goold identifies five different “copy-torts”: consumer copying, competitor copying, expressive privacy invasion, artistic reputation injury, and breach of creative control. Each of these different copy-torts, Goold argues, reflects the distinct interests that courts seek to vindicate using copyright law. Continue reading "The Plural Tort Structure of Copyright Law"

Help Support Jotwell

If you like us (lots) please consider making a donation to support JOTWELL.

We don’t charge for JOTWELL and we don’t run any ads, but producing this journal is not costless. Although all of the authors and faculty editors donate their time, we do need to pay for our server, for various types of technical and design support, and for our student editors. This adds up.

JOTWELL Needs Your Support

If every JOTWELL reader donated just $10 a year, we’d cover all of our costs. Of course, not everyone is a generous as you are, so please won’t you consider making a small gift, whether one-time or recurring, to help keep JOTWELL free (and ad-free).

Recent Donors: 2022 fund drive

Alice Abreu
Emily Achiume
Albertina Antognini
Yonathan Arbel
Reuven Aviyonah
Paul Babie
Solon Barocas
Michal Barzuza
Deborah Beim
Gerry Beyer
Sadie Blanchard
Leslie Book
Patrick Borchers
Michael Boucai
William Bratton
Khiara Bridges
Ellen Bublick
Vince Buccola
Jessica Bulman-Pozen
Colleen Campbell
I Bennett Capers
Michael Carrier
Bernard Chao
Cary Coglianese
Michael Collins
Rebecca Crootof
Wei Cui
Nestor Davidson
Richard Davis
Deborah Dinner
Sharon Dolovich
Greer Donley
James Donovan
Ingrid Eagly
Leora Eisenstadt
Andrew Elmore
Peter Enns
Luca Enriques
Kaite Eyer
Dave Fagundes
Brian Feinstein
James Fleming
Erin Fuse Brown
Stephen Galoob
Kristelia García Peterson
Aram Gavoor
Jonathan Gienapp
Robert Gordon
Andrew Granato
Bruce Green
James Grimmelmann
Hiba Hafiz
Andrew Hayashi
Michael Heller
Kristin Henning
Joni Hersch
Michael Herz
Allison Hoffman
Duncan Hollis
Vivien Holmes
William Hubbard
Clare Huntington
Anne Joseph O’Connell
Noah Kazis
Elizabeth Keyes
Daniel Klerman
Carol Klock
Nicolas Lamp
Ronald Levin
Karen Levy
Alexander Lian
Yvette Liebesman
Leah Litman
Sarah Lorr
Toni Massaro
Goldburn Maynard
Douglas NeJaime
Helen Nissenbaum
Helen Norton
Christopher Odinet
Leigh Osofsky
Nicholas Parrillo
Eloise Pasachoff
Andrew Perlman
Nicole Porter
William Price
Shalini Ray
Jessica Roberts
Gabriel Scheffler
Gabriel Scheffler
Joanna Schwartz
Colleen Shanahan
Seana Shiffrin
D’Andra Shu
Samuel Singer
Rima Sirota
Karen Sneddon
Roseanna Sommers
Kevin Stack
Gregory Stein
Lauren Sudeall
Symeon Symeonides
Nelson Tebbe
Nora Tillman
Rebecca Tushnet
Clinton Wallace
Daniel Walters
Jacob Wentzel
Woods Wilson
Gabriel Winant
Danaya Wright
Diego Zambrano
Noah Zatz

Previous Donors

Andrew Hammond
Michael Herz
Peter Lederer
Yvette Liebesman*
Timothy Lytton
Helen Norton
Scott Rogers
Sarah Swan
Sally Wise

*-Repeat donor


2015 Fund Drive Donors

Kenneth S. Abraham
Karen L. Abrams
Larry Alexander
Gerry W. Beyer
Francesca E. Bignami
Bennett Capers
Jessica Clarke
James Donovan
David F. Engstrom
James E. Fleming
Erik F. Gerding
Susan Grover
Woodrow N. Hartzog
Allison K. Hoffman
Chris J. Hoofnagle
William Hubbard
Julia Hughes
Isabel V. Hull
Lily Kahng
Anil Kalhan
Edward Kleinbard
Donald J. Kochan
Kathryn E. Kovacs
Anna Laakmann
Mark A. Lemley
Yvette J. Liebesman
Daniel Monk
Alexandra Natapoff
Douglas NeJaime
Michael Pardo
Nicole Porter
John F. Preis
Margaret J. Radin
William Sage
Joanna Schwartz
Peter M. Shane
Jacob S. Sherkow
David Sherwyn
Clyde Spillenger
Kevin M. Stack
Katherine Strandburg
Rebecca L. Tushnet
Jonathan T. Weinberg
David Zaring
Jonathan L. Zittrain

Copyright’s Family Law

Of the many things that may cause us to admire an article, one is the author’s identification of a meaningful relationship between fields that had otherwise seemed entirely disparate. In the past year, two pieces—Tony Reese’s Be Careful Where You Die and Brad Greenberg’s DOMA’s Ghost and Copyright Reversionary Interests—identified just such a non-obvious nexus between a popular issue of great social importance (marriage equality) and a relatively obscure topic of great statutory technicality (termination of copyright transfers).

Both of these articles explore issues raised by two of copyright’s distinctive future interest provisions. Descendants of authors whose copyrights vested prior to 1978 are statutorily entitled, under certain conditions, to reversionary interests in those copyrights. And heirs of any authors stand to inherit the inalienable right to terminate transfers established by the Copyright Act of 1976. The trick, in each case, is that the heirs who enjoy these potential future interests—typically, the surviving spouse and children—are determined by statute, regardless of an author’s estate plan or preferences to the contrary. Continue reading "Copyright’s Family Law"

An Information-Cost Critique of Chattel Property Servitudes

Mulligan, Christina, The Cost of Personal Property Servitudes: Lessons for the Internet of Things (July 14, 2014). Available at SSRN.

Property scholars have long noted a peculiar inconsistency between real and chattel property. While law increasingly tolerates different forms of ownership in and servitudes limiting the use of land, it has remained steadfastly resistant to such restrictions in the context of personal property. In her sharp new paper, “The Cost of Personal Property Servitudes: Lessons for the Internet of Things,” Christina Mulligan shows that this long-lamented inconsistency isn’t a problem at all, but rather a sensible distinction that flows naturally from the core differences between real and chattel property. This insight not only helps explain a longstanding puzzle in property law, but sheds new light on the increasing practice of content owners using license agreements to restrict the use of digital goods.

From a purely formal perspective, one might reasonably wonder why courts allow increasing complexity in real property ownership—from historical forms like contingent remainders and fees simple subject to executory limitation to modern innovations like condominiums and time-shares—while insisting that no such variation is permitted with respect to chattels. If I can have a defeasible fee interest or a time-share in a vacation home in Boca Raton, why not also in a Rolex or a refrigerator? This seeming has engaged scholars since Coke. Most recently, Molly Van Houweling investigated contract-based restrictions on personal property from the perspective of physical property, suggesting that the same concerns that warrant skepticism about servitudes on real property may be used to govern servitudes in the context of personal property as well. Continue reading "An Information-Cost Critique of Chattel Property Servitudes"

Unauthorized Improvement Across Property Law

Deepa Varadarajan, Improvement Doctrines, 41 Geo. Mason L. Rev. (forthcoming 2014), available at SSRN.

Scholars often debate whether intellectual property really is property at all. This is far more than just a descriptive inquiry. Asking how law regulates tangible and intangible goods differently can deliver valuable insights about the optimal governance of real property and chattels, patents and copyrights. Deepa Varadarajan’s engaging piece, Improvement Doctrines, forthcoming in the George Mason Law Review, represents an important contribution to the growing literature about what property and IP can help us learn about one another. Improvement Doctrines focuses on the fascinating but underappreciated body of doctrines in physical property law that favor—and sometimes entirely excuse—trespass and conversion that is done in good faith and that adds significant value to the res. Professor Varadarajan’s article then uses these improvement doctrines as a lens though which to analyze intellectual property’s relatively anemic attempts to take account of improving but unauthorized uses of patented inventions and copyrighted works of authorship. In so doing, Improvement Doctrines identifies and illuminates a series of fascinating problems that span both physical and intellectual property law.

Professor Varadarajan’s article begins with physical property’s improvement doctrines and moves into an investigation of unauthorized improvement in intellectual property law. In so doing, though, it neither assumes that tangible and intangible property law must mechanically mirror each other, nor insists that the differences between corporeal and incorporeal goods render any such extrapolations useless. Rather, Improvement Doctrines’ primary analytical driver is its thoughtful synthesis of the efficiency and equity rationales underlying ameliorative waste, accession, adverse possession, and mistaken improvement of land. This discussion alone yields a number of valuable insights, such as the creative point that adverse possession warrants categorization as an improvement doctrine even though its substantive law does not require enhancements to land. Continue reading "Unauthorized Improvement Across Property Law"

What Can Roller Derby Girls Teach Us About IP Law? (Answer: More Than You Think)

David Fagundes, Talk Derby to Me: Emergent Intellectual Property Norms Governing Roller Derby Pseudonyms (forthcoming Tex. L. Rev.), available at SSRN.

The orthodox justification for patent and copyright laws, at least in the United States, is utilitarian: that is, both sets of legal rules are premised on the theory that only by rewarding creators with special property rights can we ensure that creations get created.

Viewed in the abstract, who could argue otherwise?  Both technological innovations and artistic works are often difficult to create but easy to copy. Absent strong property rights, copyists will free ride on the efforts of creators. This, in turn, discourages investment in new inventions and creations. In short, copying stifles innovation – and therefore innovation requires legal intervention in the form of property rights.  Right? Continue reading "What Can Roller Derby Girls Teach Us About IP Law? (Answer: More Than You Think)"

The Public Domain Through Property’s Lens

David Fagundes, Property Rhetoric and the Public Domain, 94 Minn. L. Rev. 652 (2010).

Are patents and copyrights “property,” and does it matter?  While the question is not new in the field, David Fagundes provides a fresh perspective, arguing persuasively that the question should be understood as rhetorical rather than ontological, and that, yes, it does matter.  In Property Rhetoric and the Public Domain, Professor Fagundes aims to build upon the work of scholars working in a tradition he labels the “social discourse of property” to reorient the use of property rhetoric with respect to “intellectual property” away from a solely private rights understanding of property.  By doing so, he argues, advocates for a positive conception of the public domain will be better equipped to blunt the force of property rhetoric deployed to expand the subject matter, scope or duration of copyrights and patents.

This article follows a prior piece, Crystals in the Public Domain, 50 B. C. L. Rev. 139 (2009), in which he argues that ex ante uncertainty about user rights in copyright is a significant problem that could best be addressed by clearer boundaries between private and public rights in copyright law.  While that argument addresses the functional advantages of clearer public rights to use another’s copyrighted expression, this piece argues that there are significant rhetorical advantages to a more clearly defined public domain in copyright law.  In his words, “[b]y framing their concern about the public domain as a concern about preserving public property (rather than simply resisting property), actors concerned about this issue can restore balance to this debate.” (P. 701.) Continue reading "The Public Domain Through Property’s Lens"

WP2Social Auto Publish Powered By : XYZScripts.com